Age, Biography and Wiki

Nathan Salmon was born on 2 January, 1951 in Los Angeles, California, U.S., is an American philosopher. Discover Nathan Salmon's Biography, Age, Height, Physical Stats, Dating/Affairs, Family and career updates. Learn How rich is he in this year and how he spends money? Also learn how he earned most of networth at the age of 73 years old?

Popular As N/A
Occupation N/A
Age 73 years old
Zodiac Sign Capricorn
Born 2 January, 1951
Birthday 2 January
Birthplace Los Angeles, California, U.S.
Nationality United States

We recommend you to check the complete list of Famous People born on 2 January. He is a member of famous philosopher with the age 73 years old group.

Nathan Salmon Height, Weight & Measurements

At 73 years old, Nathan Salmon height not available right now. We will update Nathan Salmon's Height, weight, Body Measurements, Eye Color, Hair Color, Shoe & Dress size soon as possible.

Physical Status
Height Not Available
Weight Not Available
Body Measurements Not Available
Eye Color Not Available
Hair Color Not Available

Dating & Relationship status

He is currently single. He is not dating anyone. We don't have much information about He's past relationship and any previous engaged. According to our Database, He has no children.

Family
Parents Not Available
Wife Not Available
Sibling Not Available
Children Not Available

Nathan Salmon Net Worth

His net worth has been growing significantly in 2023-2024. So, how much is Nathan Salmon worth at the age of 73 years old? Nathan Salmon’s income source is mostly from being a successful philosopher. He is from United States. We have estimated Nathan Salmon's net worth, money, salary, income, and assets.

Net Worth in 2024 $1 Million - $5 Million
Salary in 2024 Under Review
Net Worth in 2023 Pending
Salary in 2023 Under Review
House Not Available
Cars Not Available
Source of Income philosopher

Nathan Salmon Social Network

Instagram
Linkedin
Twitter
Facebook Nathan Salmon Facebook
Wikipedia Nathan Salmon Wikipedia
Imdb

Timeline

1951

Nathan U. Salmon (né Nathan Salmon Ucuzoglu on January 2, 1951) is an American philosopher in the analytic tradition, specializing in metaphysics, philosophy of language, and philosophy of logic.

Salmon was born January 2, 1951, in Los Angeles to a working-class family of Sephardi Jews of Spanish-Turkish heritage.

He is the grandson of archivist Emily Sene (née Emily Perez) and oud player Isaac Sene.

Salmon attended Lincoln Elementary School in Torrance, California through eighth grade, where he was a classmate and friend of the child prodigy, James Newton Howard.

1969

Salmon graduated from North High School (Torrance) in 1969.

1971

The first person in his family to go to college, Salmon graduated from El Camino College (1971) and from the University of California, Los Angeles (B.A. 1973, M.A. 1974, Ph.D. 1979).

At UCLA he studied with Tyler Burge, Alonzo Church, Keith Donnellan, Donald Kalish, David Kaplan, Saul Kripke, and Yiannis Moschovakis.

1978

Salmon was assistant professor of philosophy at Princeton University from 1978 to 1982.

1984

In 1984, the Council of Graduate Schools awarded him the Gustave O. Arlt Award in the Humanities, for his book, Reference and Essence (1981), which was based on his UCLA doctoral dissertation.

Salmon is currently Distinguished Professor of philosophy at the University of California, Santa Barbara, and has been teaching there since 1984.

1986

His second book, Frege's Puzzle (1986), was selected by Scott Soames for a literary website as one of the best five books on the philosophy of language.

2009

He has also taught at Princeton University, UCLA, the University of California, Riverside, the University of Southern California, and was a regular visiting distinguished professor at the City University of New York Graduate Center from 2009 to 2012.

Salmon is a proponent of the theory of direct reference.

Salmon has provided accounts both of propositional attitudes and of Frege's puzzle about true identifications, i.e., truths of the form "a = b".

Salmon maintains that co-designative proper names are inter-substitutable with preservation of semantic content.

Thus, on his view the sentence "Samuel Clemens was witty" expresses exactly the same content as "Mark Twain was witty", whether or not the competent user of these sentences recognizes it.

Therefore, a person who believes that Mark Twain was witty ipso facto believes that Samuel Clemens was witty, even if he or she also believes, inconsistently, that Clemens was not witty.

Salmon argues that this is made palatable by recognizing that to believe a proposition is to be cognitively disposed in a particular manner toward that proposition when taking it by means of some proposition-guise or other, and that one may be so disposed relative to one proposition-guise while not being so disposed relative to another.

Salmon applies this apparatus to solve a variety of famous philosophical puzzles, including Frege's puzzle, Kripke's puzzle about so-called de dicto belief, and W. V. O. Quine's puzzle about de re belief.

For example, Quine describes a scenario in which Ralph believes that Ortcutt is no spy, yet Ralph also believes that the man in the brown hat is a spy, when unbeknownst to Ralph the man in the hat is none other than Ortcutt.

Under these circumstances, is Ortcutt believed by Ralph to be a spy?

The grounds for an affirmative or negative judgment seem equally balanced.

On Salmon's account Ortcutt is believed by Ralph to be a spy, since Ralph is appropriately cognitively disposed toward the proposition about Ortcutt that he is a spy when taking that proposition by means of one proposition-guise, even though Ralph is not so disposed relative to an alternative, equally relevant proposition-guise.

Salmon provided direct-reference accounts of problems of nonexistence and of names from fiction.

Salmon argues, directly contrary to Immanuel Kant, that existence is a property, one that particular individuals have and other individuals lack.

According to Salmon, the English verb "exist" is (along with its literal translations into other languages), among other things, a term for this alleged property, and a sentence of the form "a exists" is true if and only if the subject term designates something with the property, and is false (and "a does not exist" is true) if and only if the subject term designates something with the complementary property of nonexistence.

Thus Russell's example, "The present king of France exists", is neither true nor false, since France is not presently a monarchy, and therefore "the present king of France" does not designate; whereas "Napoleon exists" is simply false, since although Napoleon once existed, the moment he died he took on the property of nonexistence.

By contrast, Salmon maintains that "Sherlock Holmes exists" is literally true, whereas "Sherlock Holmes was a detective" is literally false.

According to Salmon, Sherlock Holmes is a fictional character, a kind of abstract entity, created by author Arthur Conan Doyle, and the fiction is a story, or a collection of stories, which are about that very character but are literally false.

Holmes really exists, but is only depicted as a detective in the fiction.

In the fiction, Holmes is a detective; in reality, Holmes is merely a fictional detective.

Salmon extends this view to what he calls mythical objects, like the hypothetical planet, Vulcan.

Vulcan really exists, but it is not a real planet.

It is an abstract entity that is only depicted as a planet in the myth.

Salmon's account of fiction and myth thus has direct application to the philosophy of religion.

Salmon has also applied his account of mythical objects to Peter Geach's famous problem of uncovering the logical form of the particular sentence, "Hob thinks a witch has blighted Bob's mare, and Nob wonders whether she (the same witch) killed Cob's sow".

Salmon's account shows how the problematic sentence can be true even though there are no witches, and even if Hob and Nob do not know about each other, and there is no one whom they think is a witch.

Salmon thinks, again contrary to Kant, that it is perfectly legitimate to invoke existence in a term's definition.

Thus "God" might be legitimately defined as the conceivable individual that is divine and also exists.

According to Salmon, the ontological argument for God's existence fallaciously assumes that "The F is F" is a truth of logic, or an analytic truth.