Age, Biography and Wiki

Richard Jeffrey was born on 5 August, 1926 in Boston, Massachusetts, U.S., is an American logician. Discover Richard Jeffrey's Biography, Age, Height, Physical Stats, Dating/Affairs, Family and career updates. Learn How rich is he in this year and how he spends money? Also learn how he earned most of networth at the age of 76 years old?

Popular As N/A
Occupation N/A
Age 76 years old
Zodiac Sign Leo
Born 5 August, 1926
Birthday 5 August
Birthplace Boston, Massachusetts, U.S.
Date of death 9 November, 2002
Died Place Princeton, New Jersey, U.S.
Nationality United States

We recommend you to check the complete list of Famous People born on 5 August. He is a member of famous with the age 76 years old group.

Richard Jeffrey Height, Weight & Measurements

At 76 years old, Richard Jeffrey height not available right now. We will update Richard Jeffrey's Height, weight, Body Measurements, Eye Color, Hair Color, Shoe & Dress size soon as possible.

Physical Status
Height Not Available
Weight Not Available
Body Measurements Not Available
Eye Color Not Available
Hair Color Not Available

Dating & Relationship status

He is currently single. He is not dating anyone. We don't have much information about He's past relationship and any previous engaged. According to our Database, He has no children.

Family
Parents Not Available
Wife Not Available
Sibling Not Available
Children Not Available

Richard Jeffrey Net Worth

His net worth has been growing significantly in 2023-2024. So, how much is Richard Jeffrey worth at the age of 76 years old? Richard Jeffrey’s income source is mostly from being a successful . He is from United States. We have estimated Richard Jeffrey's net worth, money, salary, income, and assets.

Net Worth in 2024 $1 Million - $5 Million
Salary in 2024 Under Review
Net Worth in 2023 Pending
Salary in 2023 Under Review
House Not Available
Cars Not Available
Source of Income

Richard Jeffrey Social Network

Instagram
Linkedin
Twitter
Facebook
Wikipedia
Imdb

Timeline

1926

Richard Carl Jeffrey (August 5, 1926 – November 9, 2002) was an American philosopher, logician, and probability theorist.

He is best known for developing and championing the philosophy of radical probabilism and the associated heuristic of probability kinematics, also known as Jeffrey conditioning.

Born in Boston, Massachusetts, Jeffrey served in the U.S. Navy during World War II.

As a graduate student he studied under Rudolf Carnap and Carl Hempel.

1952

He received his M.A. from the University of Chicago in 1952 and his Ph.D. from Princeton in 1957.

1967

This subtlety was first pointed out in terms by Ian Hacking in 1967.

However, adapting Bayes' theorem, and adopting it as a rule of updating, is a Temptation.

Suppose that a learner forms probabilities Pold(A&B)=p and Pold(B)=q.

If the learner subsequently learns that B is true, nothing in the axioms of probability or the results derived therefrom tells him how to behave.

He might be tempted to adopt Bayes' theorem by analogy and set his Pnew(A) = Pold(A | B) = p/q.

In fact, that step, Bayes' rule of updating, can be justified, as necessary and sufficient, through a dynamic Dutch book argument that is additional to the arguments used to justify the axioms.

1970

This argument was first put forward by David Lewis in the 1970s though he never published it.

That works when the new data is certain.

C. I. Lewis had argued that "If anything is to be probable then something must be certain".

There must, on Lewis' account, be some certain facts on which probabilities were conditioned.

However, the principle known as Cromwell's rule declares that nothing, apart from a logical law, can ever be certain, if that.

Jeffrey famously rejected Lewis' dictum and quipped, "It's probabilities all the way down."

He called this position radical probabilism.

In this case Bayes' rule isn't able to capture a mere subjective change in the probability of some critical fact.

The new evidence may not have been anticipated or even be capable of being articulated after the event.

It seems reasonable, as a starting position, to adopt the law of total probability and extend it to updating in much the same way as was Bayes' theorem.

Adopting such a rule is sufficient to avoid a Dutch book but not necessary.

Jeffrey advocated this as a rule of updating under radical probabilism and called it probability kinematics.

Others have named it Jeffrey conditioning.

It is not the only sufficient updating rule for radical probabilism.

Others have been advocated including E. T. Jaynes' maximum entropy principle and Brian Skyrms' principle of reflection.

Jeffrey conditioning can be generalized from partitions to arbitrary condition events by giving it a frequentist semantics.

1974

After holding academic positions at MIT, City College of New York, Stanford University, and the University of Pennsylvania, he joined the faculty of Princeton in 1974 and became a professor emeritus there in 1999.

He was also a visiting professor at the University of California, Irvine.

Jeffrey, who died of lung cancer at the age of 76, was known for his sense of humor, which often came through in his breezy writing style.

In the preface of his posthumously published Subjective Probability, he refers to himself as "a fond foolish old fart dying of a surfeit of Pall Malls".

As a philosopher, Jeffrey specialized in epistemology and decision theory.

He is perhaps best known for defending and developing the Bayesian approach to probability.

Jeffrey also wrote, or co-wrote, two widely used and influential logic textbooks: Formal Logic: Its Scope and Limits, a basic introduction to logic, and Computability and Logic, a more advanced text dealing with, among other things, the famous negative results of twentieth-century logic such as Gödel's incompleteness theorems and Tarski's indefinability theorem.

In Bayesian statistics, Bayes' theorem provides a useful rule for updating a probability when new frequency data becomes available.

In Bayesian statistics, the theorem itself plays a more limited role.

Bayes' theorem connects probabilities that are held simultaneously.

It does not tell the learner how to update probabilities when new evidence becomes available over time.