Age, Biography and Wiki
Leslie Armour was born on 9 March, 1931, is a Canadian philosopher and economist (1931–2014). Discover Leslie Armour's Biography, Age, Height, Physical Stats, Dating/Affairs, Family and career updates. Learn How rich is he in this year and how he spends money? Also learn how he earned most of networth at the age of 83 years old?
Popular As |
N/A |
Occupation |
N/A |
Age |
83 years old |
Zodiac Sign |
Pisces |
Born |
9 March, 1931 |
Birthday |
9 March |
Birthplace |
N/A |
Date of death |
1 November, 2014 |
Died Place |
N/A |
Nationality |
|
We recommend you to check the complete list of Famous People born on 9 March.
He is a member of famous philosopher with the age 83 years old group.
Leslie Armour Height, Weight & Measurements
At 83 years old, Leslie Armour height not available right now. We will update Leslie Armour's Height, weight, Body Measurements, Eye Color, Hair Color, Shoe & Dress size soon as possible.
Physical Status |
Height |
Not Available |
Weight |
Not Available |
Body Measurements |
Not Available |
Eye Color |
Not Available |
Hair Color |
Not Available |
Dating & Relationship status
He is currently single. He is not dating anyone. We don't have much information about He's past relationship and any previous engaged. According to our Database, He has no children.
Family |
Parents |
Not Available |
Wife |
Not Available |
Sibling |
Not Available |
Children |
Not Available |
Leslie Armour Net Worth
His net worth has been growing significantly in 2023-2024. So, how much is Leslie Armour worth at the age of 83 years old? Leslie Armour’s income source is mostly from being a successful philosopher. He is from . We have estimated Leslie Armour's net worth, money, salary, income, and assets.
Net Worth in 2024 |
$1 Million - $5 Million |
Salary in 2024 |
Under Review |
Net Worth in 2023 |
Pending |
Salary in 2023 |
Under Review |
House |
Not Available |
Cars |
Not Available |
Source of Income |
philosopher |
Leslie Armour Social Network
Instagram |
|
Linkedin |
|
Twitter |
|
Facebook |
|
Wikipedia |
|
Imdb |
|
Timeline
Leslie Armour (9 March 1931 – 1 November 2014) was a Canadian-born philosopher and writer on social economics.
Armour completed a BA at the University of British Columbia in 1952 and a PhD at the University of London in 1956.
At the time of his death, he was a fellow of the Royal Society of Canada and a Research Professor of Philosophy at the Dominican University College, Ottawa, Adjunct Professor of Philosophical Theology at St. Paul University, and Emeritus Professor of Philosophy at the University of Ottawa.
He taught at universities in Montana, California, and Ohio.
Armour was elected to the Royal Society of Canada in August 1998, which recognized his significant contribution to research and scholarly work.
Armour has also published some 200 papers in learned journals and chapters in books.
There is a bibliography to 2001 and extensive commentaries on Armour's work in William Sweet's Idealism, Metaphysics, and Community.
From 2004 to 2010, he was editor of the International Journal of Social Economics.
His major areas of research included metaphysics, epistemology, philosophy, the philosophical underpinnings of economics and "he is a pioneer in publishing early Canadian philosophy and has philosophical publications in metaphysics, religion, law, politics and economics".
Armour has contributed significantly to the interdisciplinary school of Canadian Studies.
He authored nine books (three with co-authors), more than seventy chapters in books and a hundred articles in scholarly journals.
He was a frequent speaker at conferences on economics, religious studies and French and German philosophy.
Armour's most recent book, Inference and Persuasion: An Introduction to Logic and Critical Reasoning (2005), was co-authored by Richard Feist.
It is written so as to be accessible to all audiences and is concerned with the problems associated with logic, offering suggestions rather than solutions, for, as Armour states, nothing is certain.
This book discusses meaning-assignment, rule-making, beliefs, and the correlation between belief and action.
It pays special attention to how these are misunderstood, corrupted and blocked so that we are robbed of our freedom.
The authors argue that reason and experience are both important to logic, and that logic is important because it allows for understanding and survival.
Inference is described as the beliefs and judgments that create rules.
Inference and rule are tools that we use for freedom.
We think for ourselves and draw our own conclusions; knowledge permits freedom to act.
Yet the way inferences are drawn is subject to the influence of logicians, such as Aristotle, and their language.
Aristotle's focus on class inclusion and exclusion highlights the limits of the language of logic.
This idea of classification is problematic, as it ignores things not included in a class and the fact that the meaning of classes is not clear.
"Trying to lay out axioms or rules in advance... will always lead to limitations" because "imposing systems on our thinking seems to bring limits into play".
Examining John Dewey's logic (Chapter Four), the notion that reason and experience are interconnected is evident.
Logic is concerned with the 'human world', which is not the 'world in itself'.
Thinking has a purpose; it is a problem solving tool, an attempt to make experience coherent.
The authors go through previous theories and views on logic and add interesting and thought-provoking ideas.
They note the tensions between experience and logic, the biases associated with reasoning, and the importance of context.
In "Logic and Morality" it is argued that our biases inform how we form our understanding of facts.
How we reason about what to do is based on practicality, which is based on our values.
In "Logic and Politics" we see the notion of classes, as assembled from members, as individualist, with community interests ignored.
The authors suggest we must understand the world through relationships, since individuals only exist in context, such as social contexts.
Logic has the tendency to either ignore social realities or create individualist societies.
Concluding their text with the limits set by the rules of logic, they state that the ultimate reason for caution in using logic is that "One should not let one's choice of logic impose restrictions on one's freedom — provided of course that one can see rational alternatives. Where that line is drawn readers must decide for themselves"