Age, Biography and Wiki

Carlos Santiago Nino was born on 3 November, 1943, is an Argentine philosopher (1943–1993). Discover Carlos Santiago Nino's Biography, Age, Height, Physical Stats, Dating/Affairs, Family and career updates. Learn How rich is he in this year and how he spends money? Also learn how he earned most of networth at the age of 49 years old?

Popular As N/A
Occupation N/A
Age 49 years old
Zodiac Sign Scorpio
Born 3 November, 1943
Birthday 3 November
Birthplace N/A
Date of death 29 August, 1993
Died Place N/A
Nationality

We recommend you to check the complete list of Famous People born on 3 November. He is a member of famous philosopher with the age 49 years old group.

Carlos Santiago Nino Height, Weight & Measurements

At 49 years old, Carlos Santiago Nino height not available right now. We will update Carlos Santiago Nino's Height, weight, Body Measurements, Eye Color, Hair Color, Shoe & Dress size soon as possible.

Physical Status
Height Not Available
Weight Not Available
Body Measurements Not Available
Eye Color Not Available
Hair Color Not Available

Dating & Relationship status

He is currently single. He is not dating anyone. We don't have much information about He's past relationship and any previous engaged. According to our Database, He has no children.

Family
Parents Not Available
Wife Not Available
Sibling Not Available
Children Not Available

Carlos Santiago Nino Net Worth

His net worth has been growing significantly in 2023-2024. So, how much is Carlos Santiago Nino worth at the age of 49 years old? Carlos Santiago Nino’s income source is mostly from being a successful philosopher. He is from . We have estimated Carlos Santiago Nino's net worth, money, salary, income, and assets.

Net Worth in 2024 $1 Million - $5 Million
Salary in 2024 Under Review
Net Worth in 2023 Pending
Salary in 2023 Under Review
House Not Available
Cars Not Available
Source of Income philosopher

Carlos Santiago Nino Social Network

Instagram
Linkedin
Twitter
Facebook
Wikipedia
Imdb

Timeline

1943

Carlos Santiago Nino (3 November 1943 – 29 August 1993) was an Argentine moral, legal and political philosopher.

1970

Nino began his academic activity in the early 1970s, concentrating on some traditional issues in jurisprudence, such as the concept of a legal system, the interpretation of the law, the debate between legal positivism and natural law, and the concept of validity.

After realizing the need to clarify the normative problems involved in some of those issues, he was led to embrace a model based on the explicit adoption of principles of justice and social morality, rejecting the predominant German-inspired "dogmatic" approach.

This signaled the beginning of his philosophical investigations, which were always oriented to practical issues, and marked by a distinctively analytical approach.

His need to provide a liberal justification for criminal law practice thus lead him to moral philosophy, and to the development of an original "consensual" theory of punishment which combined the merits of the retributive and utilitarian (see deterrence) varieties while avoiding their respective difficulties.

Similarly, the problems presented by the characterization of criminal conduct stimulated his work in the field of philosophy of action.

1977

Nino studied law at the University of Buenos Aires and at the University of Oxford, where he received his Ph.D. in 1977 with a thesis directed by John Finnis and Tony Honoré.

1980

During the early 1980s, after the restoration of democracy, Nino became engaged in politics, serving as personal assistant to President Raúl Alfonsín and as coordinator of his newly created "Consejo para la consolidación de la democracia", a special committee for the study and design of institutional reforms.

1984

His theoretical activities, however, were not forgotten: in 1984 he published his monumental Ética y derechos humanos, dedicated to Alfonsín, where he provided a comprehensive exposition of his moral thought; divided in three parts, it dealt with normative and applied ethics, as well as with meta-ethics.

This last field he expanded in a separate volume, where he adopted a constructivist approach that attempted to derive his fundamental ethical principles from the presuppositions of moral discourse, in a manner that put him, as he said, "between Rawls and Habermas".

These substantive principles, comprising the nucleus of a theory that aspired to capture the essential components of political liberalism, were the principle of autonomy, the principle of inviolability, and the principle of dignity.

The first expressed Nino's conception of the good: those things, and those things only, that were valued by the individual in question.

The second imposed deontological restrictions to the pursuit of that good, prohibiting the sacrifice of some to achieve the benefit of others.

The third principle allowed for individual consent, thus permitting persons to waive the rights recognized by the second one.

With this solid normative foundation, Nino went to tackle some practical issues, such as abortion, capital punishment, and drug regulation.

On the former, he proposed a gradualist approach similar to the American one, recognizing rights to the fetuses only when they showed the cognitive and affective capacities necessary for considering them moral persons.

As regards death penalty, he was firmly opposed to it—as he was to the criminalization of drug consumption.

1993

While on trip to La Paz, Bolivia in 1993 to work on the reform of the Bolivian constitution, Nino had an asthma attack and subsequently died.

This tragedy killed a man who appeared to be at the peak of his productivity: the year before he had published two books, served as editor to two others, and had given the manuscripts of a couple more to his friend Owen Fiss, who assumed the responsibility of readying them for publication.

1996

The Constitution of Deliberative Democracy and Radical Evil on Trial saw the light in 1996.

In the first he developed his "epistemic justification" of deliberative democracy, arguing that democratic deliberation provides better reasons to believe in the validity of moral norms than private reflection.

The second is a moving personal description of the military junta trials; it provides a testimony to his unique ability to approach public affairs with both philosophical sophistication and political commitment.