Age, Biography and Wiki
Thomas Nagel was born on 4 July, 1937 in Belgrade, Yugoslavia (now Serbia), is an American philosopher (born 1937). Discover Thomas Nagel's Biography, Age, Height, Physical Stats, Dating/Affairs, Family and career updates. Learn How rich is he in this year and how he spends money? Also learn how he earned most of networth at the age of 86 years old?
Popular As |
N/A |
Occupation |
N/A |
Age |
86 years old |
Zodiac Sign |
Cancer |
Born |
4 July 1937 |
Birthday |
4 July |
Birthplace |
Belgrade, Yugoslavia (now Serbia) |
Nationality |
United States
|
We recommend you to check the complete list of Famous People born on 4 July.
He is a member of famous philosopher with the age 86 years old group.
Thomas Nagel Height, Weight & Measurements
At 86 years old, Thomas Nagel height not available right now. We will update Thomas Nagel's Height, weight, Body Measurements, Eye Color, Hair Color, Shoe & Dress size soon as possible.
Physical Status |
Height |
Not Available |
Weight |
Not Available |
Body Measurements |
Not Available |
Eye Color |
Not Available |
Hair Color |
Not Available |
Who Is Thomas Nagel's Wife?
His wife is Doris G. Blum (m. 1958-1973)
Anne Hollander (m. 1979-2014)
Family |
Parents |
Not Available |
Wife |
Doris G. Blum (m. 1958-1973)
Anne Hollander (m. 1979-2014) |
Sibling |
Not Available |
Children |
Not Available |
Thomas Nagel Net Worth
His net worth has been growing significantly in 2023-2024. So, how much is Thomas Nagel worth at the age of 86 years old? Thomas Nagel’s income source is mostly from being a successful philosopher. He is from United States. We have estimated Thomas Nagel's net worth, money, salary, income, and assets.
Net Worth in 2024 |
$1 Million - $5 Million |
Salary in 2024 |
Under Review |
Net Worth in 2023 |
Pending |
Salary in 2023 |
Under Review |
House |
Not Available |
Cars |
Not Available |
Source of Income |
philosopher |
Thomas Nagel Social Network
Instagram |
|
Linkedin |
|
Twitter |
|
Facebook |
|
Wikipedia |
|
Imdb |
|
Timeline
Thomas Nagel (born July 4, 1937) is an American philosopher.
Nagel was born on July 4, 1937, in Belgrade, Yugoslavia (now Serbia), to German Jewish refugees Carolyn (Baer) and Walter Nagel.
He arrived in the US in 1939, and was raised in and around New York.
He had no religious upbringing, but regards himself as a Jew.
Nagel received a Bachelor of Arts degree in philosophy from Cornell University in 1958, where he was a member of the Telluride House and was introduced to the philosophy of Ludwig Wittgenstein.
He then attended the University of Oxford on a Fulbright Scholarship and received a Bachelor of Philosophy degree in 1960; there, he studied with J. L. Austin and Paul Grice.
He received his Doctor of Philosophy degree in philosophy from Harvard University in 1963.
At Harvard, Nagel studied under John Rawls, whom Nagel later called "the most important political philosopher of the twentieth century."
Nagel taught at the University of California, Berkeley (from 1963 to 1966) and at Princeton University (from 1966 to 1980), where he trained many well-known philosophers, including Susan Wolf, Shelly Kagan, and Samuel Scheffler, the last of whom is now his colleague at New York University.
Nagel is known for his critique of material reductionist accounts of the mind, particularly in his essay "What Is It Like to Be a Bat?" (1974), and for his contributions to liberal moral and political theory in The Possibility of Altruism (1970) and subsequent writings.
He is the University Professor of Philosophy and Law Emeritus at New York University, where he taught from 1980 to 2016.
His main areas of philosophical interest are legal philosophy, political philosophy, and ethics.
Nagel is a fellow of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences and a corresponding fellow of the British Academy, and in 2006 was elected a member of the American Philosophical Society.
He has held fellowships from the Guggenheim Foundation, the National Science Foundation, and the National Endowment for the Humanities.
In 2008 he was awarded a Rolf Schock Prize for his work in philosophy, the Balzan prize, and the honorary degree of Doctor of Letters from the University of Oxford.
Nagel began to publish philosophy at age 22; his career now spans over 60 years of publication.
He thinks that each person, owing to their capacity to reason, instinctively seeks a unified world view, but if this aspiration leads one to believe that there is only one way to understand our intellectual commitments, whether about the external world, knowledge, or what our practical and moral reasons ought to be, one errs.
For contingent, limited and finite creatures, no such unified world view is possible, because ways of understanding are not always better when they are more objective.
Like the British philosopher Bernard Williams, Nagel believes that the rise of modern science has permanently changed how people think of the world and our place in it.
A modern scientific understanding is one way of thinking about the world and our place in it that is more objective than the commonsense view it replaces.
It is more objective because it is less dependent on our peculiarities as the kinds of thinkers that people are.
Our modern scientific understanding involves the mathematicized understanding of the world represented by modern physics.
Understanding this bleached-out view of the world draws on our capacities as purely rational thinkers and fails to account for the specific nature of our perceptual sensibility.
Nagel repeatedly returns to the distinction between "primary" and "secondary" qualities—that is, between primary qualities of objects like mass and shape, which are mathematically and structurally describable independent of our sensory apparatuses, and secondary qualities like taste and color, which depend on our sensory apparatuses.
Despite what may seem like skepticism about the objective claims of science, Nagel does not dispute that science describes the world that exists independently of us.
His contention, rather, is that a given way of understanding a subject matter should not be regarded as better simply for being more objective.
He argues that scientific understanding's attempt at an objective viewpoint—a "view from nowhere"—necessarily leaves out something essential when applied to the mind, which inherently has a subjective point of view.
As such, objective science is fundamentally unable to help people fully understand themselves.
In "What Is It Like to Be a Bat?" and elsewhere, he writes that science cannot describe what it is like to be a thinker who conceives of the world from a particular subjective perspective.
Nagel argues that some phenomena are not best grasped from a more objective perspective.
The standpoint of the thinker does not present itself to the thinker: they are that standpoint.
One learns and uses mental concepts by being directly acquainted with one's own mind, whereas any attempt to think more objectively about mentality would abstract away from this fact.
It would, of its nature, leave out what it is to be a thinker, and that, Nagel believes, would be a falsely objectifying view.
Being a thinker is to have a subjective perspective on the world; if one abstracts away from this perspective one leaves out what he sought to explain.
Nagel thinks that philosophers, over-impressed by the paradigm of the kind of objective understanding represented by modern science, tend to produce theories of the mind that are falsely objectifying in precisely this kind of way.
They are right to be impressed—modern science really is objective—but wrong to take modern science to be the only paradigm of objectivity.
The kind of understanding that science represents does not apply to everything people would like to understand.
As a philosophical rationalist, Nagel believes that a proper understanding of the place of mental properties in nature will involve a revolution in our understanding of both the physical and the mental, and that this is a reasonable prospect that people can anticipate in the near future.
A plausible science of the mind will give an account of the stuff that underpins mental and physical properties in such a way that people will simply be able to see that it necessitates both of these aspects.
He continued the critique of reductionism in Mind and Cosmos (2012), in which he argues against the neo-Darwinian view of the emergence of consciousness.