Age, Biography and Wiki
J. L. Mackie (John Leslie Mackie) was born on 25 August, 1917 in Sydney, New South Wales, Australia, is an Australian philosopher (1917–1981). Discover J. L. Mackie's Biography, Age, Height, Physical Stats, Dating/Affairs, Family and career updates. Learn How rich is he in this year and how he spends money? Also learn how he earned most of networth at the age of 64 years old?
Popular As |
John Leslie Mackie |
Occupation |
N/A |
Age |
64 years old |
Zodiac Sign |
Virgo |
Born |
25 August 1917 |
Birthday |
25 August |
Birthplace |
Sydney, New South Wales, Australia |
Date of death |
12 December, 1981 |
Died Place |
Oxford, England |
Nationality |
Australia
|
We recommend you to check the complete list of Famous People born on 25 August.
He is a member of famous philosopher with the age 64 years old group.
J. L. Mackie Height, Weight & Measurements
At 64 years old, J. L. Mackie height not available right now. We will update J. L. Mackie's Height, weight, Body Measurements, Eye Color, Hair Color, Shoe & Dress size soon as possible.
Physical Status |
Height |
Not Available |
Weight |
Not Available |
Body Measurements |
Not Available |
Eye Color |
Not Available |
Hair Color |
Not Available |
Who Is J. L. Mackie's Wife?
His wife is Joan Meredith (m. 1947)
Family |
Parents |
Not Available |
Wife |
Joan Meredith (m. 1947) |
Sibling |
Not Available |
Children |
Not Available |
J. L. Mackie Net Worth
His net worth has been growing significantly in 2023-2024. So, how much is J. L. Mackie worth at the age of 64 years old? J. L. Mackie’s income source is mostly from being a successful philosopher. He is from Australia. We have estimated J. L. Mackie's net worth, money, salary, income, and assets.
Net Worth in 2024 |
$1 Million - $5 Million |
Salary in 2024 |
Under Review |
Net Worth in 2023 |
Pending |
Salary in 2023 |
Under Review |
House |
Not Available |
Cars |
Not Available |
Source of Income |
philosopher |
J. L. Mackie Social Network
Instagram |
|
Linkedin |
|
Twitter |
|
Facebook |
|
Wikipedia |
|
Imdb |
|
Timeline
John Leslie Mackie (25 August 1917 – 12 December 1981) was an Australian philosopher.
He made significant contributions to ethics, the philosophy of religion, metaphysics, and the philosophy of language.
Mackie had influential views on metaethics, including his defence of moral scepticism and his sophisticated defence of atheism.
Mackie was born 25 August 1917 in Killara, Sydney, son of Alexander Mackie, professor of education at the University of Sydney and principal of the Sydney Teachers College, influential in the educational system of New South Wales.
and Annie Burnett (née Duncan), who was a schoolteacher.
Mackie graduated from the University of Sydney in 1938 after studying under John Anderson, sharing the medal in philosophy with Harold Glass.
Mackie received the Wentworth Travelling Fellowship to study greats at Oriel College, Oxford, where he graduated with first-class honours in 1940.
During the Second World War Mackie served with the Royal Electrical and Mechanical Engineers in the Middle East and Italy, and was mentioned in dispatches.
He was professor of philosophy at the University of Otago in New Zealand from 1955 to 1959 and succeeded Anderson as the Challis Professor of philosophy at the University of Sydney from 1959 to 1963.
In 1963, he moved to the United Kingdom, becoming the inaugural holder of the chair of philosophy in the University of York, a position he held until 1967, when he was elected a fellow of University College, Oxford, where he served as praelector.
In 1969, he gave a lecture, "What's Really Wrong with Phenomenalism?", at the British Academy as part of its annual Philosophical Lectures series.
In 1974, he became a fellow of the British Academy.
His most widely known, Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong (1977), opens by boldly stating, "There are no objective values."
It goes on to argue that because of this, ethics must be invented rather than discovered.
In 1980 Time magazine described him as "perhaps the ablest of today's atheistic philosophers."
Mackie died in Oxford on 12 December 1981.
Mackie is said to have been capable of expressing total disagreement in such a genial way that the person being addressed might mistake his comment for a compliment.
This personal style is exemplified by the following words from the preface to Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong:
"I am nowhere mainly concerned to refute any individual writer. I believe that all those to whom I have referred, even those with whom I disagree most strongly, have contributed significantly to our understanding of ethics: where I have quoted their actual words, it is because they have presented views or arguments more clearly or more forcefully than I could put them myself."
His posthumously published The Miracle of Theism: Arguments For and Against the Existence of God (1982) has been called a tour de force in contemporary analytic philosophy.
The atheist philosopher Kai Nielsen described it as "one of the most, probably the most, distinguished articulation of an atheistic point of view given in the twentieth century."
She lectured in philosophy at the University of Birmingham from 1994 to 2004, and then at the University of Nottingham from 2004 until her death in 2022.
Mackie's son David is also a philosopher and graduated from Oxford University, where he held lectureships at Exeter College, Corpus Christi College, and Christ Church before being appointed a Fellow and Tutor at Oriel College.
He is Head of Philosophy at D'Overbroeck's College, Oxford.
His daughter Hilary is a classicist at Rice University.
Mackie is best known for his contributions to metaethics, philosophy of religion, and metaphysics.
In metaethics, he took a position called moral scepticism, arguing against the objective existence of right and wrong as intrinsically normative entities on fundamental grounds.
He was unsure what kinds of thing they would be if they existed.
His most widely known work, Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong, bluntly begins with the sentence "There are no objective values".
He uses several arguments to support this claim.
He argues that some aspects of moral thought are relative, and that objective morals require an absurd intrinsic action-guiding feature.
Most of all, he thinks it is very unclear how objective values could supervene on features of the natural world (see the Argument from queerness), and argues it would be difficult to justify our knowledge of "value entities" or account for any links or consequences they would have.
Finally, he thinks it possible to show that even without any objective values, people would still have reason to firmly believe in them (hence he claims that it is possible for people to be mistaken or fooled into believing that objective values exist).
The Times called the book "a lucid discussion of moral theory which, although aimed at the general reader, has attracted a good deal of professional attention."
Concerning religion, he was well known for vigorously defending atheism, and also arguing that the problem of evil made untenable the main monotheistic religions.
His criticisms of the free will theodicy are particularly significant.
He argued that the idea of human free will is no defence for those who wish to believe in an omnicompetent being in the face of evil and suffering, as such a being could have given us both free will and moral perfection, thus resulting in us choosing the good in every situation.