Age, Biography and Wiki

E. J. Lowe (philosopher) (Edward Jonathan Lowe) was born on 24 March, 1950 in Dover, England, is a British philosopher and academic. Discover E. J. Lowe (philosopher)'s Biography, Age, Height, Physical Stats, Dating/Affairs, Family and career updates. Learn How rich is he in this year and how he spends money? Also learn how he earned most of networth at the age of 64 years old?

Popular As Edward Jonathan Lowe
Occupation N/A
Age 64 years old
Zodiac Sign Aries
Born 24 March 1950
Birthday 24 March
Birthplace Dover, England
Date of death 2014
Died Place N/A
Nationality

We recommend you to check the complete list of Famous People born on 24 March. He is a member of famous philosopher with the age 64 years old group.

E. J. Lowe (philosopher) Height, Weight & Measurements

At 64 years old, E. J. Lowe (philosopher) height not available right now. We will update E. J. Lowe (philosopher)'s Height, weight, Body Measurements, Eye Color, Hair Color, Shoe & Dress size soon as possible.

Physical Status
Height Not Available
Weight Not Available
Body Measurements Not Available
Eye Color Not Available
Hair Color Not Available

Dating & Relationship status

He is currently single. He is not dating anyone. We don't have much information about He's past relationship and any previous engaged. According to our Database, He has no children.

Family
Parents Not Available
Wife Not Available
Sibling Not Available
Children Not Available

E. J. Lowe (philosopher) Net Worth

His net worth has been growing significantly in 2023-2024. So, how much is E. J. Lowe (philosopher) worth at the age of 64 years old? E. J. Lowe (philosopher)’s income source is mostly from being a successful philosopher. He is from . We have estimated E. J. Lowe (philosopher)'s net worth, money, salary, income, and assets.

Net Worth in 2024 $1 Million - $5 Million
Salary in 2024 Under Review
Net Worth in 2023 Pending
Salary in 2023 Under Review
House Not Available
Cars Not Available
Source of Income philosopher

E. J. Lowe (philosopher) Social Network

Instagram
Linkedin
Twitter
Facebook
Wikipedia
Imdb

Timeline

1950

Edward Jonathan Lowe (24 March 1950 – 5 January 2014), usually cited as E. J. Lowe but known personally as Jonathan Lowe, was a British philosopher and academic.

He was Professor of Philosophy at Durham University.

Lowe was born in Dover, England.

1968

His secondary education was at Bushey Grammar School, and he subsequently studied at the University of Cambridge, 1968–72 (BA in History, 1st Class), and the University of Oxford, 1972–75 (BPhil and DPhil in Philosophy).

Lowe was one of the leading philosophers of his generation.

He researched and published on a vast array of topics including: metaphysics, philosophy of mind, philosophical logic, philosophy of language, philosophy of religion, and the history of early modern philosophy.

He supervised many PhD students, working on a wide variety of topics.

He made notable contributions to developing thought on ontology, essences, dualistic interactionism, and Locke studies.

For Lowe, ontology comes in two parts: a priori and empirical.

The a priori aspect deals in the possible ways reality could exists.

The empirical aspect informs and establish what kinds of things do exists.

Thus, to grasp what is actual in the world you must also ascertain was it possible.

At the heart of his ontological world is a four-category ontology which consist of objects, kinds, attributes, and modes.

Key to his neo-Aristotelianism is a commitment to essences.

He espouses general essences and individual essences.

The view follows in the Aristotelian tradition that an essence is ‘what it is’ to be a substance.

One of his contributions was a sophisticated defense of dualistic interactionism in the philosophy of mind.

This is the view that the mind and the brain are distinct substances, and that facts about each are "causally relevant" to the other.

His work on Locke offers a charitable reading of the philosopher, and defends Locke's relevance to philosophy today.

Lowe’s four-category ontology takes inspiration from Aristotle’s Categories. His terminology emerges from the distinction that Aristotle made between ‘being said of’ and ‘being said in’ a subject: primary substances, secondary substances, attributes, and modes.

Primary substances are neither said of nor in a subject.

Secondary are said of a subject, but not in.

His own addition is to label the final two categories, attributes and modes.

Attributes are both said in and of, while modes are not said of a subject, but said in.

Attributes and modes are his own additions to Aristotle’s language.

Rather than ‘being said of’ or ‘being said in,’ Lowe introduces two distinctions: substantial and non-substantial; universals and particulars.

Thus, there are substantial particulars (objects), substantial universals (kinds), non-substantial universals (attributes), and non-substantial particulars (modes).

He argues that the distinction between kinds and modes are similar to the kind of distinction made between sortal and adjectival terms.

"The former denotes kinds of object, while the latter denotes properties of objects. Individual objects are particular instances of kinds, while the modes of individual objects are particular instances of properties."The categories and their relations are laid out in the 'Ontological Square.'

Lowe argues that his view has an advantage over other Universalist ontologies like that of David Armstrong.

That is, it does not need to rely on appeals to second-order relations.

Consider the law-statement, ‘Planets move in elliptical orbits.’ Lowe claims, according to a theory like Armstrong’s, a second-order necessitation relation obtains between the first-order properties: being a planet and moving in an elliptical orbit.

Instead, the four-category ontology would state that the law amounts to the attribute, moving in an elliptical orbit, characterizing the kind, planet

A further advantage is in the accounts ability to distinguish between dispositional and occurrent states of objects.

For example, the distinction between an object being soluble and its actually dissolving.

Where counterfactuals need a covering claim, “all things being equal,” the four-category ontology can capture the dispositions through kinds and objects."An object possesses a disposition to F just in case it instantiates a kind which is characterized by the property of being F. Thus, for example, an object O has a disposition to be dissolved by water just in case O instantiates a kind, K, such that the law obtains that water dissolves K."The modes and attributes capture the object actually dissolving by their relation to the universal of the object.

For Lowe, modes are features of an object, not constituent of it.

Here, modes are particular ways an object is.

Thus, an object may exemplify attributes dispositionally or occurrently.

It exemplifies attributes dispositionally if the object instantiates the kind which is characterized by the attribute.