Age, Biography and Wiki

Donald Brook was born on 8 January, 1927 in Leeds, England, is a Donald Brook was artist, art critic, philosopher. Discover Donald Brook's Biography, Age, Height, Physical Stats, Dating/Affairs, Family and career updates. Learn How rich is he in this year and how he spends money? Also learn how he earned most of networth at the age of 91 years old?

Popular As Donald Brook
Occupation N/A
Age 91 years old
Zodiac Sign Capricorn
Born 8 January 1927
Birthday 8 January
Birthplace Leeds, England
Date of death 17 December, 2018
Died Place Adelaide, Australia
Nationality Australia

We recommend you to check the complete list of Famous People born on 8 January. He is a member of famous artist with the age 91 years old group.

Donald Brook Height, Weight & Measurements

At 91 years old, Donald Brook height not available right now. We will update Donald Brook's Height, weight, Body Measurements, Eye Color, Hair Color, Shoe & Dress size soon as possible.

Physical Status
Height Not Available
Weight Not Available
Body Measurements Not Available
Eye Color Not Available
Hair Color Not Available

Dating & Relationship status

He is currently single. He is not dating anyone. We don't have much information about He's past relationship and any previous engaged. According to our Database, He has no children.

Family
Parents Not Available
Wife Not Available
Sibling Not Available
Children Not Available

Donald Brook Net Worth

His net worth has been growing significantly in 2023-2024. So, how much is Donald Brook worth at the age of 91 years old? Donald Brook’s income source is mostly from being a successful artist. He is from Australia. We have estimated Donald Brook's net worth, money, salary, income, and assets.

Net Worth in 2024 $1 Million - $5 Million
Salary in 2024 Under Review
Net Worth in 2023 Pending
Salary in 2023 Under Review
House Not Available
Cars Not Available
Source of Income artist

Donald Brook Social Network

Instagram
Linkedin
Twitter
Facebook
Wikipedia
Imdb

Timeline

1927

Donald Brook (8 January 1927 – 17 December 2018) was an Australian artist, art critic, philosopher, and theorist, whose research and publications centre on the philosophy of art, non-verbal representation and cultural evolution.

Brook was born in Leeds, Yorkshire, on 8 January 1927.

He was educated on scholarships at Woodhouse Grove School and at the University of Leeds, where he read Electrical Engineering.

He left before graduating with the intention of becoming an artist and was conscripted in the army toward the end of WWII.

1949

He received a Further Education and Training grant in 1949 to study sculpture at the King Edward VII School of Art in the University of Durham.

1953

After graduating (B.A. Fine arts) with first class honours in 1953 Henry Moore and William Coldstream were his external examiners, he spent a further year on a Chancellor's postgraduate award researching Archaic and Cycladic sculpture in Greece.

1962

Thereafter he established a practice as a sculptor, exhibiting at the Woodstock Gallery in London and executing commissions, and was awarded a studio and residence at the Digswell Arts Trust at Welwyn in Hertfordshire, His interest in unresolved theoretical questions about the visual arts led him to accept a further postgraduate scholarship in the Department of Philosophy in the Australian National University in Canberra in 1962.

1965

His PhD thesis (1965), examined by Professors E. H. Gombrich and David Armstrong, applied analytic-philosophical theories of perception to questions of pictorial representation and art-critical appraisal.

Electing to remain in Australia, Brook continued to work as a sculptor and as art critic of the Canberra Times under John Pringle's editorship.

1968

From 1968 he became art critic of the Sydney Morning Herald, when he was appointed as one of the three first academics in the new Power Institute of Fine Arts in the University of Sydney.

During this period (1968-1973) he was an energetic initiator of the "Tin Sheds" workshops, where his promotion of what he then called "post-object art" (more generally referred to at the time as "conceptual art") was found liberating by many of the younger artists.

1969

His 1969 John Power Memorial Lecture "Flight from the Object" proposed a radical alternative to the ideas that animated Clement Greenberg's 1968 Power Lecture "Avant-garde Attitudes".

Australian painters had generally taken their options to be restricted to the choice of international mainstream modernism or the purposeful construction of a distinctively Australian style.

1970

He initiated the Experimental Art Foundation in the 1970s in Adelaide, and was later Emeritus Professor of Visual Arts at Flinders University in Adelaide.

1973

In 1973 he was appointed to the inaugural chair of Fine Arts at Flinders University in Adelaide, where he contentiously changed the departmental name from "Fine Arts" to "Visual Arts".

He initiated theoretical studies in the psychology and philosophy of visual perception and introduced a study of Aboriginal visual culture in a context where European art history had previously dominated.

At that time no practical studio courses were offered in any Australian university.

1974

From 1974 he initiated the Experimental Art Foundation in Adelaide.

This was partly designed to enrol practising artists, along with academics and theorists, to bridge what he called "the gap between town and gown".

He also introduced postgraduate academic programs for practising artists.

Brook abandoned art criticism after leaving Sydney, and published extensively thereafter in journals of informed opinion and more popular media as well as in the academic literature.

1989

He retired from Flinders at the end of 1989 and lived in Cyprus from 1990–92, returning temporarily to a part-time role at the University of Western Australia in Perth, before settling again in Adelaide.

2008

Brook's account of art as the essentially unexpected recognition of the viability of new memes is spelled out in his book The Awful Truth About What Art Is (2008).

2014

It is succeeded by his semi-autobiographical book Get A Life (2014), in which an anthology of his papers on perception, representation, art, evolution and history is threaded together along a string of text that is intended to place them in the context of his personal history and experience.

2018

Brooks died in Adelaide in 2018.

Although they are wide-ranging, Brook's philosophical interests have centred on two principal regions of speculation: to understand the nature and place of perception and non-verbal representation in the visual arts, and to elucidate the relationship between art, the histories of works of art and the dynamics of cultural evolution.

His early work on perception was first publicly aired in "Perception and the appraisal of sculpture", in which the important distinction he later draws between matching and simulating non-verbal representational practices is introduced as a difference between what he calls the "object accounts" and the "picture accounts" that we spontaneously give of visually perceived things; notably of three-dimensional works of art.

Crucial to his thinking is the idea that non-verbal representation is not a quasi-linguistic form of communication.

It relies on the de facto socially efficacious substitutability of one thing for another thing even in cases where relevant properties are not shared.

He argues that this perceptually mediated substitutive felicity must have been available to pre-linguistic organisms or language itself could not possibly have evolved.

Brook's elucidation of the concept of art, as what he at first called "experimental modelling of actual and possible worlds", is first comprehensively spelled out in his paper "A New Theory of Art".

This rather complex theoretical structure underwent continuous modification in numerous publications as his memetic account of cultural evolution developed.

He embraced Richard Dawkins' concept of the meme as the potent factor in cultural evolution, analogous to the function of the gene in biological evolution.

However, he differed significantly from Dawkins and other meme-theorists in his way of understanding and exemplifying the meme.

Instead of offering such examples as the popular song or catchphrase he insisted that these things are items of a cultural kind analogous to the items of biological kinds such as a horse, or a cabbage.

Just as a horse is the product of appropriately activated genes, he argues that a popular song or a catchphrase is not itself a meme.

It is an item of a predictable cultural kind that is generated by exercising memes.

Memes are purposefully directed actions that can be exercised in concerted ways, as contrasted with mere behaviours.

This is first unambiguously elucidated in his paper "Art History?".